Re: MD Access to Quality

From: Matt Kundert (pirsigaffliction@hotmail.com)
Date: Thu May 12 2005 - 21:35:25 BST

  • Next message: Sam Norton: "Re: MD Access to Quality"

    Hey Mark, Sam,

    Sam caught my invisible high sign to him and jumped in on the conversation
    at the place I was hoping he would. I’m going to reconvene the conversation
    back at Mill and Aquinas, which I was using with MacIntyre in the back of my
    head (and I hoped Sam would jump in because he talks much more smartly about
    MacIntyre than I), because the part of the conversation that I’m interested
    in (which Sam has partly geared away from in the “Ideology of Capitalism”
    thread) is at work at that point.

    Matt said (May 2nd):
    it's idolatrous to think that Mill was using reason when he decided that
    liberty was the highest value and Aquinas was using something else when he
    decided love for God the highest. I have no idea what Mill and Aquinas were
    doing differently. As far as I can see, they were both “using reason.”
    They just did different things with it.

    Mark replied (May 3rd):
    The difference, I think, is in the universal accessibility of the objects of
    their thought. The concept of liberty, personal freedom, is immediately
    accessible to everyone. No one needs to be told that freedom is better than
    being buried alive. That the concept of God is not immediately accessible
    to everyone is obvious in that not everyone believes in God. Pirsig's
    Quality, like Mill's Liberty, is immediately accessible to everyone. This,
    I suggest, is why belief in God is idolatrous and belief in Quality or
    Freedom or Liberty or Equality is not.

    Sam jumped in on cue (May 3rd):
    I think this is a very revealing exchange. … But more importantly there are
    indeed societies where the concept of personal freedom is incomprehensible.
    I quote from Alasdair MacIntyre's 'After Virtue' - he's a
    philosopher/theologian I greatly admire.

    What really strikes me as odd is that, for someone so lucidly critical of
    modern ideologies in the political and economic spheres, you seem remarkably
    at home with the very same ideology in the philosophical sphere - which is
    ironic, in that it is precisely the ideology which you are here defending
    which provides the main justification for the practices which you so
    cogently condemn elsewhere.

    Matt:
    I think Sam’s right that Mark still holds to modern, Enlightenment
    philosophy for philosophical justification and, with Sam and MacIntyre, that
    this is bad. However, I think Sam and MacIntyre are wrong that
    Enlightenment philosophy provides the “main justification” for liberal
    practices. To my mind, the reason why Enlightenment philosophy is wrong is
    because it was looking for philosophical justification in the first place.
    And I think Sam and MacIntyre are subsequently wrong to think that the
    failure of Enlightenment philosophy means the failure of Enlightenment
    politics.

    If I’m right, there are basically two stages to your argument. First,
    things like personal liberty are “immediately accessible.” When this is
    shown to be suspect, by digging into history and showing how our moral
    conceptual heritage has changed, which is what Sam was pointing out, your
    second stage is to argue that a “fully realized human being” would find
    personal liberty immediately accessible. My first softening up move will be
    to point out that not everybody believes in Quality, as you say they do. To
    say that they do is to make the same move the theist does when they say that
    God exists whether particular people believe in Him or not. The only way to
    “believe in Quality” is to first have read Pirsig’s books (which not
    everyone has) and then to have been persuaded by them (which even fewer
    people have been). To say otherwise is to make the same kind of
    appearance/reality distinguishing move that Plato gave us, where
    Quality/God/whatever is there whether we like it or not.

    To begin again, the first step of “immediately accessible ideas” is suspect
    when we look into intellectual history. When Isaiah Berlin wrote about two
    concepts of liberty, negative liberty (which is Millian personal liberty)
    and positive liberty (which at the time referred to something like Marxist
    liberty), he was playing off of a point made by a French writer from the
    Enlightenment, Benjamin Constant. Constant referred to negative, personal
    liberty as Modern liberty and positive liberty as Ancient. The reason he
    formulated it so was because of the debate surrounding the Enlightenment
    thinkers on the status of the Ancient Greeks. Rousseau was prominent for
    thinking that the Ancients knew what real liberty was, and that liberty was
    the freedom found in a community, by being part of a community and acting
    for the community. Thinkers like Hume and Adam Smith were prominent for
    thinking that that wasn’t true liberty at all, and that liberty was instead
    what was gained when the community stayed out of your way to let you do what
    you wanted. Constant wrote that we stood at an Epochal changing point. The
    Ancients indeed had a notion of liberty, but it was different than ours and
    for very good reasons. Likewise, the Moderns had their notion of liberty
    which we held for good reasons. The differences lay in the changing face of
    our culture.

    This is where the second step in your argument comes into play. The
    Ancients, and other cultures and ethical modes of thinking, may have had
    their various understandings of liberty and other ethical virtues, but they
    were wrong about them, they didn’t see the moral preeminence of our way of
    thinking because they weren’t yet “fully realized human beings.” I should
    like to argue, though, that the introduction of the notion of a “fully
    realized human being” as a rebuttal in an argument begs all the important
    questions, just as supposing that some ideas are “immediately accessible”
    whereas others are not. We can fill in the blank behind “a fully realized
    human being would _________” with whatever we want, say, “be a penguin,” and
    whatever denial or argument your opponent comes up with, you can always
    reply “Well, they aren’t fully realized human beings,” which for all your
    opponent (or, as importantly, you, for that matter) knows, is true. We
    could all just be stages towards some hitherto unknown moral level. We
    won’t know until we get there, so placing our current moral understanding at
    this endpoint level begs the question over your opponent who thinks that
    their moral understanding is the better one that will last. They can reply
    the same way you do, thus creating an impasse.

    To bring this back around to the social/intellectual distinction, the
    distinction has almost always been used around here to describe the
    difference between immoral, evolutionary retardant thinking to moral,
    evolutionary expedient thinking, i.e. the difference between static and
    Dynamic. Mark put it most plainly. People often say that this part of
    Pirsig made everything so clear, it was a breath of fresh air, never having
    been done before. This always surprises the hell out of me, at least the
    last part, particularly from people who’ve read a lot of philosophy. The
    way the distinction is used, to basically denote bad thinking from good
    thinking, to my mind that distinction was created the moment Plato admitted
    in the Republic that philosophers look like run-of-the-mill rhetoricians and
    in the Phaedrus that philosophy is true rhetoric as opposed to false
    rhetoric. This distinction has been handed down to us in the form of the
    Enlightenment’s call to make our social institutions “more rational,” the
    19th century’s call to make our institutions “more scientific,” and to the
    20th century’s very idea of a “social science.” The social/intellectual
    distinction looks just like the Marxist distinction between ideology and
    science. And this is why Rand looks like a mirror image of Marx: she simply
    reverses the attributes to the higher and lower level. The problem is the
    distinction, not Marx or Rand’s attributions (at least at this point in the
    argument). The problem is thinking that you’re doing anything that your
    moral philosophical opponent cannot, like making morals “more rational,” or
    “more intellectual.”

    As MacIntyre points out in the passage Sam quoted, the problem is thinking
    that there is a Sartrean pour soi, an atom of freely choosing, freely acting
    consciousness that swings completely free of its facticity, which MacIntyre
    calls the “emotivist self of modernity.” The gist of MacIntyre’s (and
    others’) critique is that the modern notion of the true self says that it
    can choose between competing traditions of moral discourse, while itself
    being rooted in none. The “post-modern” critique is that this notion of a
    “blank self” makes no sense, and that it’s only within a tradition that any
    choices can be made. For the post-modern, socialization goes all the way
    down. I mentioned Rousseau’s famous maxim in an early post, “we are born
    free, but everywhere in chains,” and much of modernity’s problem can be
    attributed to Rousseau’s notion that we are socialized into who we are, but
    there is a true self underneath of it all that we can fully realize through
    the exercise of reason. This idea was transmitted to Kant, and so to all
    contemporary moral philosophy still hanging in his sway (which is most;
    though, I hope, lessening).

    For the social/intellectual distinction, this becomes a problem of
    recognizing that we are socially bound creatures, and that the “intellect”
    comes out of the social, but that it also somehow swings free. Just as Marx
    used the word “ideology” to mark the dirt out of which we all grow, Pirsig
    uses “social.” And Marx used “science” to mark the method by which we could
    pull ourselves out of the mud, just as Pirsig uses “intellectual.” But
    Marx, like every other Enlightenment rooted philosopher, never could
    adequately describe what we were grabbing onto to pull ourselves out of the
    mud, never could find what Daniel Dennet called a “skyhook.” And so Marx’s
    “ideology” never really amounted to more than a reference to “the bad guys.”
      And likewise I think for Pirsig’s distinction. And if that’s so, the
    distinction does very little in the argumentation that occurs between the
    good guys and the bad guys.

    Since I’ve already written part of my criticisms of Sam’s continuance of the
    MacIntyrean argument (in an “ideology of capitalism” post), I'll just add a
    little bit more here to make it a bit clearer. I claimed before and in this
    post that Sam and MacIntyre are conflating Enlightenment philosophy and
    Enlightenment politics. In Sam's array of points in the "ideology of
    capitalism" post, the point I most disagree with is point E. Sam's been
    savy enough to stay away from philosophical critique of liberalism, but I
    think it might be hidden in points B and C. But if it isn't, his point
    about the anthropology presupposed by liberalism is that the kinds of people
    that are formed by liberalism are undesirable. MacIntyre puts the point by
    saying that the cultural archetypes of modernity/liberalism are the Rich
    Aesthete, the Therapist, and the Manager. And that this is bad. The
    problem with this critique is that I can't see that it suffices to
    counteract our modern belief that freedom might be one of the most important
    moral goods we can have, and that if we have freedom, everything else will
    work itself out (eventually). So, maybe the Aesthete, Therapist, and
    Manager are bad archetypes to have. But those can be changed. I don't
    think they are demanded by liberalism. One of the ways they can be changed
    is by critiques like MacIntyre's, which are basically moral pronouncements,
    much like most of literary criticism is built of moral pronouncements ("this
    stuff over here (be it Harry Potter or cultural archetypes), that's bad").
    But what I can't imagine changing is the basic structure of liberal
    democracy. These critiques will all take place within the basic structure,
    because if they don't, they had better show in great detail a better
    socio-political system alternative to liberal democracy, which is not what
    MacIntyre, for one, has done.

    I’ll end by saying something more about the notion of a “fully realized
    human being.” While I don’t think such a notion helps in an argument with
    an opponent who already disagrees with you on the end result, the notion,
    like the notion of a “fully realized polity,” does play a part in our moral
    thinking. For “post-moderns,” it is important to sketch the utopias we’d
    like to see realized because it helps us think up concrete suggestions for
    realizing them. It gives us a direction to go. It also helps us begin the
    channels of communication between alternative utopias described by others.
    The existence of plurality and diversity poses a significant challenge to a
    community. The first step is communication, spelling out the various
    traditions and cultures people are coming from, their different ends, goals,
    and desires, and then trying to figure what we are going to do about it.

    The gist of my criticism of the social/intellectual distinction is that,
    while it may serve a function in describing the tradition you’re in (though,
    as I’ve said, I think the MacIntyrean line is effective in making that
    particular way of describing it suspect), it won’t serve much of a function
    in deliberating about what we are going to do about disagreement, it won’t
    play much of a role in the argumentative dialogue that unfolds after
    understanding (well, actually it usually unfolds during the process of
    understanding, but that’s another matter).

    Matt

    p.s. Mark commented last time that my little array of levels (“inorganic –
    rocks; biological – plants, animals; social – social customs; intellectual
    – independently manipulable symbols”) was “a terrible over-simplification of
    [Pirsig’s] metaphysical hierarchy.” That may be true, but it wasn’t mine.
    It was more or less Pirsig’s in his “Letter to Paul Turner,” which is still
    accessible on the moq.org main page.

    MOQ.ORG - http://www.moq.org
    Mail Archives:
    Aug '98 - Oct '02 - http://alt.venus.co.uk/hypermail/moq_discuss/
    Nov '02 Onward - http://www.venus.co.uk/hypermail/moq_discuss/summary.html
    MD Queries - horse@darkstar.uk.net

    To unsubscribe from moq_discuss follow the instructions at:
    http://www.moq.org/md/subscribe.html



    This archive was generated by hypermail 2.1.5 : Fri May 13 2005 - 02:16:31 BST