RE: MD Rhetoric

From: Matt Kundert (pirsigaffliction@hotmail.com)
Date: Tue Oct 18 2005 - 21:24:43 BST

  • Next message: Case: "RE: MD Any help"

    DMB,

    DMB said:
    I think there's a HUGE difference between "insisting on a particular
    description" and objecting to some particular descriptions such as this [the
    brain state] one. To describe the mystical experience in terms of brain
    states is classic SOM reductionism.

    Matt:
    A description is only reductionistic if it adds, after the details of the
    description, "this is how things really are." This is not how non-reductive
    physicalists describe things. They say, "Here's a description of a table in
    terms of molecules" or "Here's a description of an experience in terms of
    firing neurons." So are you saying that a mystical experience cannot be
    described in terms of firing neurons _at all_? If that's the case, how do
    you get around my objection that you're insisting on a particular
    description?

    DMB said:
    ...one gets the impression that Rorty is a SOMer whose critique of
    philosophy consists largely in rejecting the idea that there is an
    epistemically accessable reality beyond the appearances. He's rejecting the
    correspondence theory because there is no way for the pre-existing subject
    to correspond with this pre-existing physical reality. And yet he seems to
    be working within the belief that we are psychological creatures in a
    physical world. As I understand it, Rorty has decided to simply declare that
    philosophy is impossible because of this unbridgable gap.

    But Pirsig rejects the correspondence theory, not because the gap is too
    wide, but because it is a product of mistaken assumptions, metaphysical
    assuptions about subjects in an objective reality.

    Matt:
    I think you have a slightly mistaken impression about what Rorty is up to.
    Rorty's detailed critique of the correspodence theory (or
    representationalism or SOM) is parasitic on those terms, of working with
    them and saying, "And how are we ever to bridge that gap?," pretty much as
    you say (though not exactly because its less about materialism then you
    think). But after he gets to that question, he says that we should probably
    just ditch the Cartesian, S-O, knower/known problematic, just as you say
    Pirsig does. In this sense, they are doing the same thing. The gap is a
    product of mistaken assumptions, so we should ditch the assumptions that
    create the gap. (You see Pirsig doing the same thing, making parasitic
    arguments, in the S/O Dilemma in ZMM. And then he just rejects the whole
    problematic after seeing that arguing with it won't work.) That's why the
    classical pragmatists were accused of idealism. As the little snipet from
    the Oxford thing said, the pragmatist's argumentative strategy is basically
    the same as the 19th century idealists. What the idealist didn't do is go,
    "Well, we should ditch the problematic," they just went, "Well, that's what
    we have to deal with." (This is why I think Pirsig wants to hitch his train
    up to idealism at various points and why he shouldn't.)

    What I'm criticizing the pre-/post- and pure/impure distinction of is
    resurrecting that problematic. You're right, Locke conceived of the
    distinction in terms of sensory perception, but its not the sensory
    perception that's the problem, its the distinction. If we get rid of the
    distinction between passive receptivity and active judging (which is what
    Kant was working with and Northrop inherits from him), we won't have a
    problem with reducing everything to sensory perception, as traditional
    British empiricists wanted to do, or brain states and logical properties, as
    the logical postitivists, heirs of the British empiricists, wanted to do
    because we won't be _reducing_ anything. We'll just be throwing out various
    proposals for descriptions for different purposes.

    To focus on what you're saying about the stove example, you accuse me of
    "insisting that quality is in the subject, in the valuing." I think it only
    looks that way to somebody who makes a distinction between the two, object
    valued and subject valuing. I think this is exactly the distinction you are
    in danger of making when you gloss the hot stove example by saying, "this
    paragraph is CONTRASTING 'pure sensation' or 'immeditate experience' with
    the intellectual constructs or 'creative judgements' that quickly follow."
    We _shouldn't_ be contrasting the two in this way. This is the contrast
    that the British empiricists and the Kantians wanted to make. You're almost
    _forced_ to make the invidious distinction between subjects and objects
    after making that distinction, and that's why its bad. The S/O distinction
    would no longer be optional (dependent on purpose) as Pirsig wants it, it
    would be roughly as Bo wants it, the intellectual level or something, a
    necessary part of the nature of human knowing. If you make a distinction
    between pure value and subsequent valuing, I think you are forced to ask
    such silly questions as, "Well, what's doing the valuing? What is it
    valuing?" You don't want to do that. I thought Pirsig's insight was to
    make it all _valuing_ across the board (which is still parasitic on the old
    language and why it looks like reducing everything to one side, the subject,
    as the idealist did). Rocks are interplays of valuings, patterns of
    valuing. Everything from the touch of a physical object to the hearing of
    an idea for the first time are interplays of valuing, not the passive
    reception of value and then the active valuing later.

    DMB said (in the other post):
    The difference between looking at art and talking about art was very far
    from my point and I certainly think you're smart enogh to know the
    difference without anyone having to point out such a thing. I'm simply using
    the examples that Pirsig uses in trying to talk about experiences that are
    pre-intellectual, pre-linguistic, ineffable. The hot stove, the new song
    heard on the street and the paintings of El Greco are all used as examples
    of when Dynamic Quality becomes noticable to Westerners like us. I'm not
    trying to reduce DQ to commonsensical "gut reactions" or to the simple act
    of shutting your mouth for a while. And by the way, Matt, we very much agree
    about "gut reactions". People who live by such impulses are doomed to
    hedonism, fascism or some other short-sighted self indulgences. Its a
    degenerate road to ruin. I think its downright creepy to equate "gut
    reactions" with a "primary empirical experience".

    Matt:
    Well, alright, I know you're not _reducing_ DQ to gut reactions (and I
    totally expected you and everyone else to agree on not wanting to be
    hedonists), but your description of this amorphous thing called "primary
    empirical experience" is parasitic on such examples. Its what gives it its
    shape. You're building, as you say is the only way possible, by analogy.
    I'm trying to point out that this analogy doesn't pan out very well. I
    think you'd have to be committed to, if not hedonism, at least impulsivity.
    You're trying to explain the DQ/SQ distinction by way of analogy, but the
    series of analogies set up are not only different from each other (creating
    a bewildering array of uses for DQ), they try and get you to accept
    seperable, specifically philosophical theses from common sense distinctions,
    like "gut reactions" and "further reflections." Taking the hot stove again,
    I think Ian played out the description of DQ and SQ fairly right according
    to the standard view you're elaborating on. There's your initial reaction
    to the stove, and then there's your further reflections about the initial
    experience. What I don't see is how this is (should be) tied in with the
    other things that go under the heading of DQ, like as ultimate reality. It
    seems like a mistake to me.

    The one thing I think it facetious to say is that, "Despite my ignorance on
    this point [about the overcoming of traditional empiricism], it seems
    reasonable to assume that the traditional empiricists were operating within
    a SOM framework while Pirsig isn't." It might be reasonable as a leaping
    off point into an investigation into the matter, but it isn't a safe
    assumption if you don't know anything about the matter. I've been trying to
    raise doubt about whether we should take Pirsig's word for it or not about
    what he's overcome or hasn't. But to take another example, what about my
    trust in Rorty? Don't I take his word for it? Sort of, but not in the same
    way. The difference between Rorty and Pirsig is that Rorty's left a large
    corpus of writing and Pirsig hasn't. Having woven my way through most of
    that corpus, I've seen him excercise his arguments in a number of different
    situations and contexts. Whether or not one thinks the arguments successful
    or not, if you read them you'll know how to predict what Rorty thinks about
    a wide range of matters. With Pirsig, we have a much smaller set of
    contexts that we've seen Pirsig write about. So it requires us to
    extrapolate from what he does say. In working out those extrapolations,
    from his arguments against defined opponents and his connection points with
    the history of philosophy, I've come to think that it isn't all neat and
    clear.

    The only way for me to make my point about this is to rehearse traditional
    empiricism, rehearse what Pirsig does, and then rehearse the critiques of
    empiricism that mangled _it_ to pieces and see if any of them bear any
    relation to Pirsig. I'm not prepared to do all of that at the moment (no
    less in a post or series of posts). All I have right now is my, shall we
    say, gut reaction. From what I have read and thought about, I'm not so sure
    about Pirsig's escape from representationalism. From where I am currently,
    I'm not convinced, as David says, that Pirsig is a step beyond Rorty.

    One of the things my gut reactions tell me is that we should be wary of
    Pirsig's descriptions of SOM. I've mentioned for a while that I think
    Pirsig conflates two enemies in an unhelpful matter, representationalism and
    materialism. I think we can see that played out in your descriptions of the
    problem. You keep pegging me with some kind of reductive materialism, when
    the only problem I can see with materialism was that it was reductive. I
    suspect that Pirsig conflated the two primarily because they were conflated
    through much of history. But we know its not required, if for no other
    reason than the early rationalists, like Descartes, Leibniz, and Spinoza,
    and the idealists, like Berkeley and Hegel. I think looking at the
    vicissitudes of the history of philosophy gives one a greater appreciation
    of the range one's philosophical attitudes can take.

    The other reason I would go off on a little spree of what most will consider
    "negligible philosophology" is because I think one of the reasons people get
    into trouble is they're focused on building a system of philosophy from the
    ground up, but without really knowing why they're building it.
    Philosophical systems were built to solve certain problems. Richard McKeon
    is often blasted as a degenerate taxonomist of philosophical thinkers (which
    is one of the things Pirsig was reacting against in his distaste for the
    Chairman, though I don't think he makes any explicit mention of it), but the
    one thing that McKeon taught is that to understand what a philosopher was
    doing when he built such-and-such philosophical edifice is what _problems_
    the philosopher was tangling with. What gave the philosopher _impetus_ to
    build the system.

    You've been quoting Pirsig at me when I ask _why_ you would want
    such-and-such distinction, but that's not all I want. I pretty much know
    what Pirsig thinks he was doing, what he says in the books. What we need is
    some sense of why the problems Pirsig is setting out to dissolve are
    problems and what these problems are. And when some of these problems are
    traditional philosophical problems (not all of them are), I think the only
    way to be able to get a good sense of whether Pirsig's solution is
    successful or not is to have a good sense of the history of that problem, of
    why Pirsig picks it up as a problem from the history of philosophy.
    Everytime you tell me that this or that distinction doesn't fall into this
    or that agreed upon bad distinction, I start to wonder _why_, then, do we
    need the distinction you're selling? If I can use the gut reaction/further
    reflection distinction just as easily as the pre-/post- distinction in that
    situation, what other situations is the pre-/post- distinction helping me
    in?

    At this present moment, my basic criticism of your use of the impure/pure
    sensation distinction is that, if Ian reframes it successfully in the terms
    he does, it should make us wonder why we need a pre- and post-intellectual
    experience distinction when we already have a common sense distinction
    between "gut reactions" and "further reflections." Because if that's _all_
    the pure/impure sensation distinction amounts to, then it looks superfluous
    because there _wasn't_ a problem there to begin with. We already _have_ the
    distinction between gut reactions and further reflections. But if I had to
    guess, I don't think either you or Pirsig thinks that that's all there is to
    the distinction. That being the case, I think using analogies that boil
    down to the distinction between reaction/reflection obscures what you think
    you're getting out of the pre-/post- distinction that I'm not.

    The thing I think you and Pirsig are reacting to heavily in this regard is
    Socrates' definition of the "life of knowing" as the highest form of life
    (which was, I think, a large part of why Pirsig made the distinction between
    classic and romantic in ZMM). I agree in this reaction (and so did people
    like Nietzsche). I think there are many more forms of life that are just as
    good, there are many more things we do then philosophy that is good,
    pleasureable, and needed like politics (which we still agree on despite our
    philosophical differences) and sunsets and paintings. But I don't think
    this route in displacing Socrates' definition of the philosophical life is
    the right one. I think its something like overkill. I think all we need is
    the ole' Millian, democratic point that what you do in your free time is up
    to you. All we need is the very simple, commonsensical point against
    elitism, "different strokes for different folks."

    The thing that I think leads Pirsig into some dangerous situations (from my
    perspective) is his blending of what we might call practical wisdom with
    philosophical wisdom (what Pirsig would probably call philosophological
    wisdom). He has some great practical advice and he has some great
    philosophical advice. I think things get tangled and bogged down when he
    tries to say something systematic about all of it. He tries to link
    together the sense that we shouldn't devalue the life of a non-thinker (the
    romantic person from ZMM) with the dissolution of the historical
    philosophical problems of S/O, free will, substance, etc. I'm not sure that
    we should try and deal with all of those problems in the same breath. (And
    more to the point, what if we don't? Is there a problem with dealing with
    them separately?)

    I think the most neutral terms of describing the disagreement we've found
    might be something like this: we disagree on the nature of SOM, the impetus
    that prompts Pirsig into formulating some alternative to it. The shape and
    scope of this enemy is going to shape _our_ response to it, determine what
    we take out of Pirsig, which is why you think one part of Pirsig fundamental
    and I a different part. If there is a further direction to this
    conversation, it'll have to be about what _we_ consider SOM to be (not
    _just_ what Pirsig considers it, though obviously it'll travel through there
    considerably), what we consider the impetus to philosophize to be, what
    problems we consider ourselves to be solving.

    Matt

    MOQ.ORG - http://www.moq.org
    Mail Archives:
    Aug '98 - Oct '02 - http://alt.venus.co.uk/hypermail/moq_discuss/
    Nov '02 Onward - http://www.venus.co.uk/hypermail/moq_discuss/summary.html
    MD Queries - horse@darkstar.uk.net

    To unsubscribe from moq_discuss follow the instructions at:
    http://www.moq.org/md/subscribe.html



    This archive was generated by hypermail 2.1.5 : Wed Oct 19 2005 - 15:23:29 BST