Re: MD Clearing up Bo's intellectual mess, Part III

From: Matt Kundert (pirsigaffliction@hotmail.com)
Date: Wed Jun 29 2005 - 23:17:24 BST

  • Next message: Matt Kundert: "Re: MD Clearing up Bo's intellectual mess, Part II"

    ...from Part II

    (If you've forgotten, Pirsig's about to start talking about mind/matter
    again, so pay attention.)

    “What is essential to understand at this point is that until now there was
    no such thing as mind and matter, subject and object, form and substance.
    Those divisions are just dialectical inventions that came later. The modern
    mind sometimes tends to balk at the thought of these dichotomies being
    inventions and says, ‘Well, the divisions were _there_ for the Greeks to
    discover,’ and you have to say, ‘_Where_ were they? Point to them!’ And
    the modern mind gets a little confused and wonders what his is all about
    anyway, and _still_ believes the divisions were there.” (382)

    This is a difficult to passage to interpret. Leaving aside Pirsig’s
    allusion to his “discourse on Western ghosts” (the same passage that Bo
    disavows as idealist clap-trap, which should raise a question as to how
    committed Bo is to his own historical narrative), I want to focus on how
    whether we should interpret Pirsig as saying that the _Greeks_ created the
    divisions, or whether they were created by somebody else. Bo wants to
    suggest that the Greeks created all of those divisions together, that SOM,
    issuing from the subject/object dichotomy, all came together in a heap. I
    don’t think they did. I think Pirsig shunts all of them under the SOM
    mantle (for very good reasons), but I don’t think the Greeks created them
    all. To interpret this passage as suggesting that the Greeks created them,
    Bo will hammer down on “_until now_ there was no such thing as…”. He will
    point back to the paragraph before where Pirsig fingers Anaxagoras as one of
    Socrates’ teachers.

    To loosen the hold of this suggestion, I want to again remind people that
    Anaxagoras wasn’t a literal teacher of Socrates. I think his placement in
    the previous paragraph has nothing to do with suggesting that the
    mind/matter dichotomy existed or was created by the Greeks, but that its
    there to remind _us_, us “modern minds,” that the “mind” is important. When
    I read that paragraph, I will hammer down on “Those divisions are just
    dialectical inventions that _came later_.” When Pirsig says that the modern
    mind balks and says that these divisions were “_there_ for the Greeks to
    discover,” I think we have to be careful about taking it too literally. I
    think the important bit is Pirsig’s reference to the “modern mind.” For the
    modern mind, we do have these distinctions. But I think we need to gloss
    forward Pirsig’s statement that they “came later” and remember that Pirsig,
    a page before, says that the “first conscious search for what was
    imperishable” was what “spelled a whole new level of transcendence for the
    Greek civilization.” When Pirsig goes on to talk about what Plato and
    Socrates did, he doesn’t talk about mind or matter, subject or object, form
    or substance. He says that Plato and Socrates, “are defending the Immortal
    Principle of the Cosmologists against what they consider to be the decadence
    of the Sophists. Truth. Knowledge. That which is independent of what
    anyone thinks about it. The ideal that Socrates died for. … He damns them
    because they threaten mankind’s first beginning grasp of the idea of truth.”
    (383) And then: “And yet, Phaedrus understands, what he is saying about
    Quality is somehow opposed to all this.” (384)

    I want to suggest that ZMM is much more of a journey then Bo lets on.
    Pirsig is tracing the trail of his enemy through history. His first
    important stop is with the Subject/Object Dilemma. That is a specifically
    _modern_ dilemma. It didn’t arise with the Greeks, the Greeks didn’t think
    about it or consider to give answers to it. But Pirsig is going backwards
    through our philosophical history to find the root cause of our problems.
    So he deals with the SOD (I might add, unsuccessfully at that point), but it
    is only a stage in his hunt. He (we) learn something from the encounter and
    what we learn is that the dilemma is all wrong. So we ask: why is it here?
    Part IV is the finishing of Pirsig’s hunt. He traces the modern dilemma
    back to the Greeks. So what began the chain of events? “Parmenides made it
    clear for the first time that the Immortal Principle, the One, Truth, God,
    is separate from appearance and from opinion, and the importance of this
    separation and its effect upon subsequent history cannot be overstated.”
    (382) He’s right, it can’t be. Parmenides gave us the appearance/reality
    distinction. We must penetrate beyond appearances, beyond shifting opinion,
    to the imperishable, immortal reality. Pirsig doesn’t say that Anaxagoras’
    identification of the Immortal Principle with _nous_, “mind,” had importance
    that couldn’t be overstated. Anaxagoras gets _one line_. His placement
    with Parmenides as Socrates’ teachers is to remind us where we came from and
    where we are going back to with the wisdom we find in the past.

    After the appearance/reality distinction was made important, the Sophists
    came along and contradicted them. They said that “their object was not any
    single absolute truth, but the improvement of men. All principles, all
    truths, are relative.” (383) But they didn’t have the tools to win. They
    didn’t have a way of distinguishing between probable knowledge and absolute
    knowledge. All the Greeks had was opinio and episteme, crappy opinion and
    perfect knowledge. What Plato did to destroy the Sophists was create a
    method for going from opinio to episteme: dialectic. This was the creation
    of epistemology. Parmenides created metaphysics by distinguishing between
    appearance and reality, and that distinction _demands_ an epistemology, a
    method, criteria for being able to tell opinion about appearances from
    knowledge of the imperishable reality. At the heart of SOM, then, is that
    distinction (appearance/reality) and the demand for a method. Through the
    vicissitudes of time, it turned into its modern progeny: “The whole purpose
    of scientific method is to make valid distinctions between the false and the
    true in nature, to eliminate subjective, unreal, imaginary elements from
    one’s work so as to obtain an objective, true picture of reality.” (236)

    To supplement this story, I should provide a history of how metaphysics and
    epistemology spawned modern SOM. I clearly don’t have enough room here. I
    will suggest this, though: the mind/matter problem didn’t become a problem
    until Descartes. The subject-object idiom didn’t become solidified until
    Kant. If you want a little more meat to these suggestions, I can direct you
    to the narrative I tell in January, 2005 in the MF (look that up). Don’t
    get me wrong though. The Greeks clearly had some sort of concept for
    “mind,” _nous_ as Pirsig said. But--_nous_ isn’t exactly what we mean by
    mind. And the Greeks had some sort of concept for “matter,” maybe _phusis_
    (which roughly translates to “nature”). What I’m saying is that there
    wasn’t a mind/matter _dualism_, which spawned off its own particular
    problems that we are familiar with, until the modern period. It is, in
    fact, partly what marks off the beginning of the modern period of
    philosophy. So, for instance, the Greeks would not have understood Pirsig’s
    Subject/Object Dilemma.

    I’ll end this long exposition with some short, bullet-point conclusions of
    Bo’s project:

    1. If subject-object is coextensive with mind-matter, then Pirsig never
    treated them as central to the intellectual level (if anything, it would
    have to be appearance/reality). This refutes Bo’s, “I have the true MoQ
    because it was the first one.”

    2. If SOM is coextensive with the mind/matter dualism, then it did not
    arise with Socrates, Plato, Aristotle, etc. This refutes Bo’s simple
    co-optation of Pirsig’s narrative of the rise of SOM.

    3. If SOM (as mind/matter) is the intellectual level, then you’re caught
    with an interface problem: How does mind hook up to matter? This catches
    you in the problems of epistemology which Pirsig’s identification with the
    Sophists was supposed to elude.

    4. If SOM (as mind/matter) is the intellectual level, then you’re stuck
    with scientific realism: Only what corresponds to matter is objective
    knowledge. Everything else is solely about the mind, and so subjective.
    This catches you into the problems of scientism, which is part of what
    Pirsig was trying to destroy.

    Matt

    p.s. By the way Bo, apropos Scott: you may be confused about this, but
    people can understand and still disagree (in fact, they have to understand
    before they can disagree). Maybe I need to add some caps or exclamation
    points here to help you understand this, but I'd like to see you disagree
    with that statement. It'd be a fun excusus into paradox.

    _________________________________________________________________
    Express yourself instantly with MSN Messenger! Download today - it's FREE!
    http://messenger.msn.click-url.com/go/onm00200471ave/direct/01/

    MOQ.ORG - http://www.moq.org
    Mail Archives:
    Aug '98 - Oct '02 - http://alt.venus.co.uk/hypermail/moq_discuss/
    Nov '02 Onward - http://www.venus.co.uk/hypermail/moq_discuss/summary.html
    MD Queries - horse@darkstar.uk.net

    To unsubscribe from moq_discuss follow the instructions at:
    http://www.moq.org/md/subscribe.html



    This archive was generated by hypermail 2.1.5 : Wed Jun 29 2005 - 23:57:06 BST