MD The Populist Persuasion

From: Matt the Enraged Endorphin (mpkundert@students.wisc.edu)
Date: Mon Dec 09 2002 - 00:02:53 GMT

  • Next message: Harry L. Stille: "RE: MD MOQ FOR DUMMIES, Please"

    Dear All,

    I thought of something provocative the other day, so I thought I'd let you
    all know ;-)

    One of my favorite words for a while after reading Lila was
    "philosophology." Etymologically, it captured its prey perfectly: "the
    study of the love of wisdom." As a beginning philosophy student who's
    favorite philosopher was someone I would never study in a class, it was an
    important invective. As I matured, however, I began to use the word less,
    particularly as I moved into education. And then, as I read and absorbed
    more and more Rorty, I had to come to terms with what Pirsig meant. It
    looked more and more as though Pirsig would call Rorty a philosophologist,
    while retaining the title philosopher for himself. But, because of my
    general liking of both Rorty and Pirsig, what did that really mean?

    I was reflecting on the term philosophology and its uses when I hit upon an
    interesting theme: populist rhetoric. Pirsig styles himself a rhetorician
    in ZMM, and an able one at that, and anyone that lasts long on this list
    has to be an able rhetorician themself. What struck me is the type of
    insulation and defense of his philosophy that Pirsig is preparing for
    himself in the opening of Chapter 26. The first three pages are part of a
    recurring theme of distrust of the academic establishment that drowns out
    the other theme in Chapter 26, a theme that recurs just as much: the
    synthesis of other thinkers and texts.

    The rhetoric of Ch 26 is that of populism. The rhetorical strategy of
    populism is to create a rhetorical community of "plain people," among whom
    a large majority of people would include themselves, appeal and speak for
    them on their behalf, and rail against the elites who are trying to
    subjugate and oppress the community of regular people you are speaking on
    behalf of. Pirsig's target is the academic, ivory-tower elites and Pirsig,
    in appealing to those who distrust the well-mannered eggheads, will find no
    end of allies.

    This language tends to simplify things, however. Its a rhetorical strategy
    that also resembles the Marxist tactic of identifying whoever disagrees
    with them as "bourgeois." Pirsig, and the rhetorical community he
    represents, can now relegate his enemies to a lower, unrespected position.
    This is a strategy that occurs all the time here, and one I have
    participated in propagating and been the object of.

    But the question should be, is this a good strategy? The creation of
    rhetorical communities is unavoidable, but we should be careful about the
    types of communites we create and be aware of the possible co-optation of
    those communities. At the bottom of Pirsig's community is an untenable
    position of contrasting philosophology to philosophy. And the MoQer is
    then given free reign over labeling others as either not thinking
    creatively enough for themselves, i.e. being under the spell of the
    academic elites who have given our hero Pirsig the short shrift, or not
    sticking to Pirsig's message as relayed by his writings, i.e. being under
    the spell of the academic elites who have given our hero Pirsig the short
    shrift.

    The philosophologist, as defined by Pirsig, is a "derivative, secondary
    field, a sometimes parasitic growth that likes to think it controls its
    host by analyzing and intellectualizing its host's behavior." Philosophy,
    then, is the opposite of this. Its the substance that philosophology
    studies. Pirsig links philosophology with other parasitic fields like art
    history, art appreciation, musicology, and literary criticism. This gives
    us an insight into what Pirsig is talking about: history and criticism. If
    he had wanted to be thorough in his examples, he would've said art history,
    art criticism, music history, music criticism, literary history, and
    literary criticism. His targets are those who catalog the history of a
    discipline and those that theorize about a discipline, rather than actually
    participating in a discipline. So his targets are philosophy history and
    philosophy criticism. This is where the problems begin.

    If we take art and music as our first two examples, the problem will
    present itself. The first question is, "Can art and music students do
    without art history and music history?" At first one might think, "Sure,
    why not? What does it matter if a really good painter knows who Monet and
    Picasso are? Why does a singer need to know about Schoenberg and what he
    was up to? I'm sure they're not thinking of any of them when they're
    singing and painting." At first the demand to know the history of your
    discipline seems like a reactionary thing to demand. Made by the old-guard
    before the avant-garde changes the rules. If that was all there was to
    this, just some left over snobbery from the old establishment, it might
    seem well enough to chalk this difference of opinion over philosophology to
    a difference in opinion about whether Verdi's La Traviata or Madonna's
    "Like a Prayer" is more respectable. Over whether pop singers who are
    classically trained (like Mariah Carey) are more respectable then those who
    are not (like Brittany Spears). Over whether there is a thing called
    <ahem> "bullshit" art.

    But after this initial thought, I would have some questions about how a
    person, ignoring history and tradition, learns how to sing or paint. If
    you ignore everything done in the past, will you turn out to be a great
    singer or painter? Will you, indeed, even know who to draw or sing a note?
     The answer is, "Yes, possibly." One can train themselves in all sorts of
    activities. If a person grew up in the wild and heard no music and talked
    to no musicians, had no contact with the outside world, and had a guitar,
    it is possible that the person could teach herself how to play like Jimmy
    Page without ever having heard of Jimmy Page. Is it statistically likely?
    I doubt it.

    What I'm driving at is the common empiricist claim that pragmatists hold
    with Pirsig: we are born tabula rasa. Despite tacit agreement with Kant on
    certain kinds of a priori knowledge, Pirsig would largely agree that humans
    do not have innate ideas about anything, they learn them. Take his example
    of the baby in Ch 9: "One can imagine how an infant in the womb ACQUIRES
    awareness of simple distinctions such as pressure and sound, and then at
    birth ACQUIRES more complex ones of light and warmth and hunger." (emphasis
    mine) The operative word is "acquire." Babies aren't born knowing
    anything. They acquire patterns of behavior through time. So my question
    would be, "How does a baby grow up to be Jimmy Page or Monet or Verdi? Or
    even Brittany Spears?" They have to emulate them. If our little baby
    doesn't want to be any of these people, let's say she just wants to sing or
    paint, how is she usually taught? By belting out notes? By taking a brush
    and spilling paint everywhere? If a baby spilled paint all over a table,
    would we say she was painting? The answer: depends.

    You can see that I'm being extremely evasive so far. The problem is that
    all of these questions depend on contingent circumstances. They depend on
    a community of people saying, "Yes, the baby is painting," or "No, she was
    just reaching for her bottle of milk." This kind of answer, of course,
    shows my true spots, but someone who believed in an objectively true way of
    painting would have to agree that the answer does depend on some people
    saying yes or no (though, they would follow that with a, "And one group
    happens to right and the other wrong"). Either way, the answer depends on
    a tradition of answering the question in a certain way. What I'm driving
    at is that when a person learns how to paint or sing, they are learning how
    to paint or sing like other people have sung or painted. They are
    inadvertantly taking part in a tradition, a tradition that has history, a
    history that is inadvertantly being learned.

    When we turn back to literature and philosophy, we can see what problems
    we're going to run into if we keep up with our distinction between
    philosophology and philosophy. In literature, the problem of doing
    creative writing without learning a little history of writing is pretty
    obvious. When a person _literally_ not knowing how to write writes,
    "OJDLF(#)(Uoijwfj03jdkpdsijoler," because they _literally_ don't know how
    to write (which goes along with reading), we are hesitant to say that they
    are adding a valuable brick to our cultural wall (even when our daughters
    at a young age write it). If a fourth grader writes a book that starts
    with, "And I have a cat. He smells like: Toast, and stuff; eveytime," and
    this book is slammed by every literary critic in the US, the kid can reply
    with the same rhetorical-community generating response that Pirsig gave:
    "Ya' know what, you lame-o' egg-heads? You guys are just jealous that you
    can't write. You're just a derivative field that lives and dies off the
    stuff I write. You're just pissed because I'm writing literature and
    you're writing about literature."

    In philosophy, distinguishing between a discipline's history and its
    substance becomes untenable. How would we even know we were doing
    philosophy unless Socrates told us we were? There are many different
    definitions of what philosophy is and isn't, but let me forward this
    Rortyan one: you are doing philosophy when you fit in a tradition of other
    people who are identified as philosophers. Pirsig's a philosopher because
    he's reflecting on questions that Socrates asked BECAUSE HE READ SOCRATES
    (or, rather, Plato). Pirsig's reacting wildly against the whole academic
    establishment of philosophy, but I'm not sure he's hit his mark with his
    distinction between people who read philosophy and people who do
    philosophy. Going back to the two subsets of philosophology, philosophy
    history and philosophy criticism, its difficult to seperate where people
    are doing philosophy and where they're criticizing other people's
    philosophy. Socrates' position is defined in part by its criticism of the
    Sophists, the Sophists' position by its opposition to the Cosmologists, the
    Cosmologists position by its opposition to Homer, and on and on, ad
    infinitum. If we drive what Pirsig's saying to its natural consequences,
    it would apear that Pirsig's asking us to ignore whatever the philosophical
    community has to say about him because they are just bitter about being
    unable to do real philosophy. Under this guise, though, it would appear we
    could say any damn thing and call it philosophy. Afterall, in a bout of
    overkill he says, "philosophers ... are a null-class. They don't exist.
    Philosophologists, calling themselves philosophers, are about all there
    are." Well, if the list of contemporary philosophers is so small, I wish
    Pirsig could have provided us with that list so we know who we can trust.

    Pirsig goes on to say in Ch 26 that, "the best way to examine the contents
    of various philosophological carts is first to figure out what you believe
    and then to see what great philosophers agree with you." This quote
    punches up two points I want to make. First, taking an empiricist, tabula
    rasa image of learning, I don't know what a person could end up believing
    if they never read anything. Pirsig seems to be saying that we will
    naturally begin to think like Socrates even if we never read him. I find
    this a bit incoherent with the tabula rasa image that it would appear
    Pirsig also holds. Secondly, if we suspend the way Pirsig appears to want
    us to generate beliefs (out of thin air) and go with a more traditional
    picture of belief generation (read some stuff, think about it, generate
    some beliefs; read some more stuff, think about it, generate and revise
    some more beliefs), then Pirsig is saying a very Rortyan, syncretist thing:
    look at intellectual history as the task of finding heroes and villians.
    Take your belief structure and fit it on top of what they are saying. In
    other words, Pirsig's endorsing the Bloomian idea of "strong misreadings"
    and (or, at the least) the Rortyan idea of narrative construction.

    The point on Harold Bloom is also important because Bloom offers, in The
    Anxiety of Influence, a portrait of how great writers are created. Taking
    off from the phrase, "those who ignore history are doomed to repeat it,"
    Bloom says that great writers are great because they understand what's come
    before them and they desperately want to be greater than that. Because of
    this, they are always anxious about being influenced because they
    desperately want to say something new. Pirsig reflects this anxiety in his
    distinction between philosophology and philosophy (including the quote Wim
    just recently pointed out to DMB in the "Symbolically or actually?" thread)
    and when he says (in response to the question, "Are there any books that
    you feel inspired you in your writing of ZMM?"), "there's an adage to
    remember, 'Reading is the enemy of writing.' ... Any time I did read a book
    during the years of writing ZMM and Lila it would stop the writing for as
    much as a week while memories of what I just read or heard gradually
    faded." This would explain why Pirsig's such a poor scholar, but it also
    shows him desperately wanting to say something new without being influenced.

    The quote on how to read philosophological carts also elaborates on the
    rhetorical strategey taken by some here. For instance, Bo took a purist
    line when he said to me (after my first post on the connections between
    Pirsig and Rorty), "Everybody seem [sic] to read books and then return to
    the forum insisting that the MOQ is to be seen through the eyes of the last
    read author. I know that tendency from before...." ("Re: Confessions of a
    Fallen Priest," Tue Aug 06 2002 - 13:19:40 BST) This line is also taken
    (or, at least, implied) by Sam when he said recently, "sometimes we get
    distracted by our own preconceptions." It seems that if we follow Pirsig,
    without any distracting preconceptions, we'd have to go isolate ourselves
    up on a mountain to generate some preconceptions to be distracted by.
    Against this, I read Pirsig as 1) being misguided in his distinction
    between philosophology and philosophy (even though there is something to
    rail against in contemporary, academic philosophy) and 2) tacitly endorsing
    a Rortyan/Bloomian conception of reading.

    Somehow, I hope against all hopes that Pirsig doesn't believe any of the
    stuff I've driven his position to say. For, against the grain of his wish
    to meditate alone on a mountain, he takes the time to read his history of
    philosophy to co-opt a few allies and disparage a few enemies. The
    Sophists, Poincare, and James and Plato, Aristotle, and Boas, respectively,
    just to name a few. Pirsig is a synthesizer at heart. He wants to say all
    things to all people. Why else would he co-opt American pragmatism and
    Eastern mysticism? Why else would he take the time to see if Quality fits
    in the Daodejing in place of Dao? These aren't things someone who wants to
    be new does. These are things a syncretist does. At root, I think ZMM and
    Lila oscillate between Pirsig's desire to say something new and his desire
    to colligate formerly opposed ideas and traditions.

    Matt

    MOQ.ORG - http://www.moq.org
    Mail Archive - http://alt.venus.co.uk/hypermail/moq_discuss/
    MD Queries - horse@darkstar.uk.net

    To unsubscribe from moq_discuss follow the instructions at:
    http://www.moq.org/md/subscribe.html



    This archive was generated by hypermail 2.1.5 : Mon Dec 09 2002 - 00:33:25 GMT